Nearly
every Christian, I suppose, has had the
experience of being belabored by unbelievers about the putative sins of what
is termed organized religion the Spanish Inquisition,
the trial of Galileo, the Salem witch-hunts, and so forth. What surprises me
is that Christians have been so slow to turn the argument around and point
to the record of what we may call organized irreligion.
Since we Christians
regard faith as a gift, we seldom resent unbelief as such. You cant
very well blame someone for not having received a gift, but there are those
who angrily reject gifts, or who resent the good fortune of those who do
receive them, or who are otherwise something other than
people who dont happen to be religious in all innocence.
If religion can be
evaluated as a social phenomenon, in terms of its visible effects on human
behavior, so can unbelief. To begin with the most colossal example, the
militant atheism of the Soviet Union has resulted in the murder of tens of
millions of people on grounds of their mere membership in so-called
counterrevolutionary or reactionary classes. Graham Greene contends that
the Inquisition might have killed that many people, had it been technologically
feasible to do so, but we may doubt this. The Inquisition executed tens of
thousands of people over several centuries for what were at least treated
as individual crimes. Just or unjust, these executions were judicial in form
and were performed against persons, not classes. The perversions of
Christianity are also to some extent limited by Christianity. The perversions
of atheism recall Dostoyevskys famous remark, If God does
not exist, then everything is permitted.
This or that atheist
may protest against Dostoyevskys inference, but the fact remains
that many atheists have made the same inference themselves.
Enlightened atheists sometimes sneer at Christians who behave themselves
only because they fear hellfire and it may be true that there are
higher motives for good conduct but it is hardly consistent to make
this criticism and then to assume simultaneously that such Christians will
keep behaving themselves once they cease believing in the afterlife.
I can imagine one kind of
atheist let us call him the pious atheist who
arrives at his unbelief without joy, simply as an intellectual conclusion. I
suppose such a man would regard Christian civilization with the kind of
affection and respect a Roman convert to Christianity in Augustines
day would feel for the dying Roman Empire, for Cicero and Virgil and Marcus
Aurelius. He would feel that, although that world had passed away, it had left
much of enduring value. We actually do see pious atheists who may regret
the Inquisition but who also cherish Dante, Monteverdi, Spenser, Milton, Bach,
Handel, Dr. Johnson. To cease believing in the viability of this Christian
civilization is not necessarily either to condemn it or to assume an attitude
of enmity toward it.
 Yet there is another
sort of atheist who does regard himself as Christendoms enemy. Far
from cherishing its past, he condemns it and would wipe out every trace of it
in the present. He hates and fears every sign of it: the Catholic Church,
Moral Majority, the inscription In God We Trust. He thinks that
humanity is now free at last from dogma and superstition, and he would get
on with the business of creating a new world on progressive and scientific
principles. The difference between the two kinds of atheists is roughly the
difference between Santayana and Sartre.
Richard Weaver wrote
that a person has no right to advocate any reform of the world unless he
shows by some prior affirmation that he does indeed cherish some aspects
of the world as it is. Our pious atheist meets this test. He sees the passing
of the Christian order as a highly equivocal development, if a necessary and
inevitable one. He knows he lives in a continuing world, and he has the grace
and wisdom to appreciate Christianity as an attempt to express, however
imperfectly, truths about that world. If he finds some who still believe, he is
not altogether eager to correct them. He understands Gonzalos
rebuke to Sebastian in The Tempest:
My lord Sebastian,
The truth you speak doth lack some gentleness
And time to speak it in.
And he understands the reflection of Henry V:
There is some soul of goodness in things evil,
Would men observingly distill it out....
The pious atheist,
moreover, will not be so sanguine about what is to succeed the Christian
order. For him the mere negation of God is, in itself, no cultural substitute
for the Christian myths and symbols that have shown their power to sustain
generations of human beings. Atheism in itself has no cohesive force.
Whatever social cohesion it has provided so far has come more from its
destructive hostility to the Christian civilization it has totally failed to
improve on. Looking at the organized masses of his fellow atheists, the pious
atheist may prefer erring with Augustine to being right with such as these.
The godless order has
brought us Communism and abortion clinics. It has yet to produce its Homer,
Virgil, Shakespeare, or Dante. We can understand the man of no religious
faith feeling that he at least prefers the company of the believers to that of
the current pack of unbelievers.
It may be that the
characteristic evils of the twentieth century dont necessarily follow,
in strict logic, from the denial of Gods existence. The historical fact
remains that they have followed. As the Marxists say, it is no accident. If it
is fair to hold believers responsible for the actions of Christians as an
identifiable historical body organized religion
then it is equally fair to hold unbelievers responsible, too.
Yet we persist in
treating atheism as if it were nothing but a private cognitive matter, of no
public concern, eligible for the conventional protections we accord to, say,
the varieties of Protestant belief. For some people it may be that, but it is
time to recognize that atheism is also a systematic, organized, and socially
powerful negation, driven by furious hostility to religious tradition.
Personally, many of its votaries are boorish and indiscriminate in their
refusal to give Christianity real credit for anything; they have no desire to
assimilate anything of its heritage, even those parts Christianity itself
assimilated from its various pagan heritages.
The militant-atheist
animus belongs to what I have elsewhere called the alienist
animus, the willfully estranged attitude toward the general society typical of
modern intellectuals and found, in various ways, among some so-called
minority groups. The fault lines of alienism dont really coincide with
obvious social lines of division. It may occur more often among, say, Jews,
than among Mormons, it may be increasing among Catholics as it decreases
among Jews, but its occurrence can never be predicted in the individual case
on the basis of group membership. In fact, some so-called minorities, such as
gays, are not even minorities by inheritance.
Some numerical
minorities, like Mormons, arent even thought of as minorities in the
subtle special sense of the word now current. That word virtually embodies a
presumption of disaffection from the general society, and this disaffection
is itself presumed to be justified by what is termed the minoritys
victimization at the hands of a more or less monolithic majority. If we look
more closely, I believe we will even find that the very idea of a minority in
this sense is largely a rhetorical device for covertly attacking what remains
of the Christian culture.
Tension and hostility
between different ethnic and credal groups is natural, but it is also a
reciprocal affair: neither side is likely to be wholly innocent. Still, the
Christian side, as it happens, is likely to have a certain Christian willingness
to give a charitable benefit of doubt and to assume a share of the guilt. It is
only natural for the non-Christian or anti-Christian side to accept this favor
without returning it. For this reason Christians in the modern world have
been slow to recognize and respond adequately to their enemies even
their declared enemies.
When an intellectual
tells us that the white race is the cancer of history, clearly
using the white race as a surrogate for historical Christendom, we
are hearing something other than the voice of the disinterested intellect. We
are hearing an expression of nihilistic hatred. Unbelief as such does not impel
this kind of fanaticism.
 It is remarkable that we
have been so slow to recognize this specific form of hatred, so much in
evidence, as a social problem or even as a social phenomenon. The language
abounds in words signifying the hatreds, fears, and suspicions of cultural
insiders toward outsiders. We are all acquainted with racism,
ethnocentrism, xenophobia, anti-Semitism,
nativism, and the like; these words have a certain hothouse quality
about them, suggesting their recent invention to serve particular needs.
Even older words such as prejudice, bias, bigotry,
discrimination, and hatred itself have taken on the same
anti-majoritarian connotations, although it is humanly probable that there is
hostility of at least equal intensity in the opposite direction. We have no
specific vocabulary at all to suggest this reciprocal possibility.
Yet disaffection from
the society one inhabits is always an available attitude. A glance at
Shakespeare confirms this. His plays offer a gallery of characters who, for
one reason or another, have chosen an attitude of antagonism toward their
societies. Some, like Shylock, are not without provocation; some, like Iago,
indulge the universal temptation to envy, with no real excuse. Shylock gives
his angry reasons; Iago cant explain himself except to himself
and he is struck dumb when, his full villainy exposed, his society
confronts him.
For our present
purposes, Edmund in King Lear may be the most interesting
example. Presumably Shakespeare doesnt believe in the gods Lear
believes in, but he clearly doesnt care for Edmunds cavalier
attitude toward them. The pious characters Lear, Cordelia, Kent,
Edgar are all shown as Edmunds moral superiors, whatever
their other defects. We know little about Shakespeares own religious
beliefs, but he patently respects a societys right to its sense of the
sacred, to the shared symbols of holiness held in common by unreflective
people which is to say, by most people in their unreflective moments.
Almost without
exception, Shakespeares alienated characters are
villains enemies of social peace and order. They are recognizably
human, and they sometimes appeal powerfully to our sympathies, but there
is no doubt of their villainy in action. Their villainy consists precisely in their
active enmity toward the society around them. The apostate is also a social
defector.
The assumptions
embodied in the very structure of these plays are directly opposed to the
assumption that hatred and hostility are always to be imputed to society.
This imputation itself expresses hostility, and we do well to raise our guard
against those who make it. Whatever atheism may mean abstractly, in our
own world it often means a specific and militant hatred of Christianity, a
hatred as particularist as anti-Semitism, and as deadly.
This essay originally appeared in Center Journal (Spring 1985) of
Notre Dame University, Notre Dame, Indiana.
Joseph Sobran
Article copyright © 2006 by The Vere Company. All Rights
Reserved.
This article may not be reprinted in print or
Internet publications without express permission
of The
Vere Company.
|
Send this article to a
friend.
|
|
Return to the SOBRANS
home page.
|