How Old Was Oxfords
Daughter, and When Did William Lose His Hair?
A reply to Alan Nelson
by Joseph Sobran
Alan H.
Nelsons review of my book Alias Shakespeare, in the Fall 1999 issue of
The Shakespeare Quarterly, actually reviews two books: the
one I wrote, and the one I didnt write.
The one I wrote argues that the
Shakespeare works were actually written by Edward de Vere, seventeenth
Earl of Oxford, not the legendary William of Stratford; and that the
strongest evidence of Oxfords authorship lies in the Shakespeare
works themselves, particularly the Sonnets. Any refutation of the book I
actually wrote must therefore concentrate on my reading of the
Sonnets.
Oxfords supporters may be
pleased to learn that Professor Nelson, without realizing it, makes fatal
concessions to my thesis in the very act of trying to refute it. Gail Kern
Paster, editor of The Shakespeare Quarterly and extremely
scornful of the authorship question, surely didnt
realize what Nelson was giving to the enemy either, or she would never
have agreed to publish his review. More on this later.
But let me deal with the unwritten book
first. Nelson notes that I (1) am not a scholar, (2)
dont claim to be, (3) have done little or no original
research, and (4) make about ten factual errors in my book. Yet he
immediately forgets that the book is a polemic and judges it harshly as
what it is not: a work of research. Most of the inaccuracies he notes occur
in a single chapter, a biographical sketch of Oxford; they are incidental to
my argument. In the end Nelson sneers that Im a would-be
literary historian, thus dismissing another claim I dont
make.
True, I dont pretend to be a
scholar; I have no credentials beyond a bachelors degree and an
English major. But in my view the balance of nature requires that some of
us nonscholars be able to detect fraudulent scholarship. That is what
Alias Shakespeare is meant to do.
Bogus scholarship is especially rife in
academic Shakespeare studies, which are based on the dubious dogma that
William of Stratford was, beyond doubt, the poet-dramatist we call
Shakespeare. The scholars, their reputations at stake,
cant afford to admit that there is any question whatsoever about
this. Alias Shakespeare tries to show how badly they have
erred in their own field, by belittling and ignoring ample evidence that
William didnt write the Shakespeare works and that Oxford
did. They literally dont know the first thing about their subject:
who he was.
With Stalinist discipline, the academic
party line requires Williams partisans to deny that there is any
room for reasonable doubt of Williams claim (or rather, the claim
made for him, which he may never have made himself), and to insist that
those who do doubt his claim have never, in more than a century of
controversy, raised a single valid point. Contrary evidence must be
belittled or ignored, at whatever cost in logic. Nothing may be conceded to
the enemy, whose slightest blunder must be magnified into proof of his
total incompetence. Nelsons review of Alias
Shakespeare satisfies all these requirements, charging me with
amateurism and junk scholarship, among
other things.
Nelson, himself a scholar who has done
valuable research on Oxford, faults me, with heavy sarcasm, on such
factual matters as Oxfords eldest daughters age, the time
of his mothers remarriage, his military service, and the cause of
his death. It may be that Nelson is correct on all these things
Im perfectly willing to defer to his specialized knowledge
but none of them are more than marginally relevant to the Shakespeare
authorship question. He specializes in pedantic nit-picking, or what might
be called Gotcha! scholarship as if a mistake about
Oxfords hat size would defeat any case for Oxfords
authorship.
As Nelson says, Alias
Shakespeare relies on the published or unpublished efforts
of others (including myself) [which are] minimally
acknowledged. He sounds miffed that I didnt give him more
credit. Actually, I wrote in my acknowledgments: Alan Nelson of
Berkeley has shared his precious discoveries with equal
generosity. Did he expect to be credited with co-authorship?
I was indebted to Nelson chiefly for
copies of a few letters of Oxford, one of which is quoted in Alias
Shakespeare. My gratitude to him was (and is) sincere. But this
was not, in truth, a great debt, though he may prefer to think
otherwise.
More specifically, I had deep
reservations about Nelsons judgment concerning his own
discoveries. Ive known him for some years. Time and again
hed unearth a fascinating document, only to make outlandish
inferences from it. He was quick to embrace the idea that Oxford was
bisexual, but he seemed to regard this as something to discredit Oxford
with, rather than a detail to be disinterestedly assimilated to a fuller
picture. In a debate with me in Seattle a few years ago, he proffered an
eccentric theory that (as I understood him) Oxford didnt hear very
well and consequently had no ear for poetry. He seemed driven not to
explain Oxford, but to explain him away. Alan always struck me as a
pleasant fellow, but a little confused. A certain amount of research is
indispensable, but like the rest of us the scholar must also possess
literacy, logic, comprehension, presence of mind,
fair-mindedness, and simple common sense.
For the purposes of Alias
Shakespeare, I generally relied on B. M. Wards 1928
biography of Oxford still the only one available for the
facts from which I argued. Another biography, correcting Wards
mistakes and incorporating recent discoveries, is long overdue; Nelson
himself is writing a new one, and it may improve on Ward, unless, as I
apprehend, its warped by Nelsons uncontrollable hostility
to Oxford.
But Alias Shakespeare
isnt a biography. It is, obviously, an entirely different sort of book,
a frankly argumentative book, using what were (apparently) undisputed
facts as my starting point. If Ward erred here and there, Nelsons
snide remarks should have been directed at Ward, not me. Even so, Ward is
generally solid. If he committed only ten small errors in his whole book,
he did well, as biographers go; as we shall see, there is little reason for
confidence that Nelson will do better. At any rate, I fail to see how I can
be blamed for trusting Ward on the essential facts, where he seldom goes
wrong, even on Nelsons hypercritical showing.
Capitalizing on Wards scattered
errors (while disingenuously ascribing them to me), Nelson adopts a
supercilious pose of
near-omniscience about Oxford. Yet he makes no attempt to show that
these errors vitiate my argument. It doesnt depend on them;
Id have made exactly the same argument from the facts as Nelson
would have them. What difference does Oxfords daughters
age (whether she was fourteen or fifteen in 1590) make to the question of
whether Oxford wrote the Sonnets? Nelson offers no explanation. He
cant see that such details arent germane to the authorship
debate, as I tried apparently without success to explain to
him in Seattle.
By shuttling between my argument and
his own rather catty factual quibbles, Nelson makes his review of
Alias Shakespeare an extended non sequitur. Like most
academic scholars confronting anti-Stratfordian arguments, he avoids a
genuine debate by framing the dispute as one between competent
professional scholars (such as himself) and hopelessly incompetent
amateurs. The reader is invited to assume that its inconceivable
that the experts could be wrong and the amateurs right.
Perhaps understandably, Nelson wants to
evaluate Alias Shakespeare in terms of his own specialty
rather than the books avowed purpose. As a researcher, hes
inclined to insist that original research is essential even when it clearly
isnt. But his harping on minutiae may signify no more than a normal
human desire to see ones own occupation as indispensable; and
scholars are notoriously self-important. What is less innocuous is
Nelsons evident feeling that his special knowledge of
Oxfords life from primary sources makes him Oxfords most
authoritative (and severest) judge. He seems to regard the differing
judgments of others, less informed than he is, as somewhat impudent, and
any praise of Oxford annoys him.
Nelsons eagerness to disparage
his subject doesnt suggest the ideal temperament for a biographer.
He says cynically that Oxfords high literary reputation in his own
time rested more on rank than on talent. He doesnt
tell us how he knows the copious contemporary praise of Oxford was
insincere, but his assertion implies that the many men who generously
praised Oxford, including Edmund Spenser, were all toadies. Nelson also
says that Oxfords high reputation was nowhere
memorialized until 1622 though in fact it had been
affirmed in print many times by 1598.
Nelson is determined not to give Oxford
credit for anything, let alone for being Shakespeare. His scholarship is
further flawed by his inability to distinguish between a criticism and an
insult. Thus he dismisses Oxfords elegant 1573 letter to Thomas
Bedingfield as a dense thicket of literary banality, as if his
personal opinion (which I find
tin-eared) constituted objective evidence of Oxfords lack of
talent.
Uninhibited by intellectual rigor, Nelson
insinuates that to detect factual flaws in Alias
Shakespeare, however minor, is to disprove Oxfords
authorship. A logician he is not. He even has trouble stating my argument
accurately, reducing it to his own coarse paraphrases. He says I charge
that Ben Jonson lied through his teeth in the First Folio and,
even more preposterously, that I accuse Jonson of being
bribed to do so. What I actually wrote is very different.
Of course I think Jonson must have been a
knowing party to the Folios concealment of Oxfords
authorship; but I never charge him with a culpable lie on that account. I
merely think he, and Oxfords other friends, were respecting
Oxfords own wishes for posthumous privacy. As I wrote:
Pembroke gave Ben Jonson generous patronage and no doubt did a
good deal to arrange his appointment as poet laureate; he of all men was
in a position to secure Jonsons cooperation in the fiction that
William Shakspere was William Shakespeare. To extrapolate from
this benign conspiracy a charge that Jonson lied through his
teeth and was bribed is a cynical reduction. But such
nuances are lost on Nelson.
Nelson says the major
premise of Alias Shakespeare is that [a] clear
relationship must necessarily exist between the works and the life of an
author. Since no such clear relationship (whatever
that means) exists between the Shakespeare works and William of
Stratford, it follows (according to Nelsons account of my
reasoning) that William wasnt the author.
Nelson quips that whoever the author
was, he couldnt have had first-hand experience of
ancient Rome or the Trojan War; as if Id made the absurd
contention that everything in the Shakespeare works, including ghosts and
witches, must necessarily correspond to something in the
real authors life.
But of course I dont hold the
simple-minded major premise Nelson attributes to me. I
have no idea what he thinks hes paraphrasing when he represents
this sloppy syllogism as my view. I must say its tedious to have to
keep saying what I actually wrote, as opposed to what Nelson says I
wrote. A competent book reviewer (not to mention a scholar) should be
able to summarize a books contents with dispassionate
accuracy.
Nevertheless (and we now come to the
book I did write), I assume that authors often do disclose
something of themselves in their fictions. Literary biographies of writers,
from Dante to Hemingway, have sought to show how their works were
inspired, shaped, and colored by their personal lives.
Can this be done for Shakespeare? I think
so, and I think we have enough evidence in the works themselves to make a
powerful case that Oxford was the author, not because those works
must necessarily (as a universal a priori truth) disclose
their authorship, but because, as it happens in this particular instance,
they actually do so.
None of the countless biographers of
William have ever shown from the internal evidence of the works that
there is any reason, apart from external testimony, to believe William
wrote them. They merely insist that the external testimony is conclusive,
though many distinguished writers and actors Henry James, Walt
Whitman, Mark Twain, John Galsworthy, Sigmund Freud, Clifton Fadiman,
Charles Chaplin, Orson Welles, John Gielgud, Derek Jacobi have
found it incredible.
My real major premise is
that if the Shakespeare works seem to reflect Oxfords life,
letters, experience, and personality, while totally lacking similar
resemblances to William of Stratford, we may fairly suspect that Oxford
was the real author. The disparity in probability between Oxford and
William is overwhelming: the case for Oxfords authorship can be
found in the Shakespeare works, especially the Sonnets, whereas the case
for Williams authorship rests entirely on testimony. After all,
testimony (such as that of the Folio) may be purposely false or misleading.
The authors self-disclosures, especially if they are as oblique as
those of the Sonnets (which have no need to identify the author directly,
since they address a reader who already knows him intimately), are likely
to be more trustworthy.
Oxfords champions always appeal
to the Shakespeare works; Williams champions rarely do. I once
asked an academic scholar how, if those works had been published
anonymously, he would prove Williams authorship; he had no
answer. How could he? If the Shakespeare works hadnt been
ascribed to William in the first place, nothing within them would ever
have led anyone to suspect that William had written them. If, on the other
hand, they had been ascribed to Oxford by the 1623 Folio, nobody would
ever have doubted Oxfords authorship. The works fit his profile as
closely as Paradise Lost fits Miltons.
Setting aside the Sonnets for a moment,
a good case for Oxfords authorship can be made from
Hamlet alone. The play reflects several events and persons
in Oxfords life, chiefly in Polonius and his children, who strongly
resemble Oxfords father-in-law, Lord Burghley, Burghleys
daughter (Oxfords pathetic wife), and Burghleys two sons.
The author knew a good deal about Burghleys family life, as Oxford
did and William couldnt. The play also echoes Oxfords
letters in ways Nelson has failed to notice: one of those letters complains
of the delay of the law, and another refers to the
proverb about the silly horse that starves while waiting for
the grass to grow. The verdict of Se defendendo in an inquest into
Oxfords killing of a servant is echoed in the gravediggers
blundering Se offendendo. Hamlet, like Oxford, is
captured by pirates in the English Channel. Oxford probably wrote the play
in late 1588, after his wifes early death; it was first mentioned by
Oxfords friend Thomas Nashe in 1589, which orthodox scholars,
inventing facts to preserve their dating system and, thereby,
Williams authorship, have mistaken for an allusion to a supposed
ur-Hamlet whose existence has never been proved, only
inferred. This ur-Hamlet is the supreme example of the
nonexistent document on which the case for William depends.
No one of these details, by itself, proves
Oxfords authorship; but collectively they gain force, especially in
conjunction with other facts about Oxford. They form what John Henry
Newman called converging probabilities, and the more of
such provocative details we find, the more improbable it becomes that
they are all coincidences, especially if they have explanatory power.
Oxfords long visit to Europe, for example, helps explain several
Shakespeare plays set in Italy and showing intimate knowledge of the
country. The names of two of Oxfords Italian friends, Baptista
Nigrone and Pasquino Spinola, appear conflated in the name of Kate the
Shrews father, Baptista Minola.
Nelson doesnt deny that Oxford
spent a year in Italy, but he lamely counters that it is not
impossible that William of Stratford traveled there too,
perhaps in a company of players. With not
impossible and perhaps, you can prove just about
anything, however improbable, for which there is no positive evidence. We
know that Oxford visited at least several of the cities in which
Shakespeare plays are set; its extremely unlikely that William,
who apparently never left England, could have seen all the same cities (let
alone met Nigrone and Spinola). These and many other details that Nelson
doesnt deny point to Oxford.
There is no must
necessarily about it. The relation between an author and his work
is more indirect and subtle than that, which is why it might be hard to
show from internal evidence that, say, Agatha Christie wrote the Hercule
Poirot novels, and why we usually settle for the name on the title page.
Aristotle cautions us against seeking more certitude than the nature of
the subject admits of.
At key points Nelson falls back on the
argument that if we knew more about William, his authorship would
or might appear less improbable. He says that
perhaps Williams life was less humdrum than it
appears, and that the Sonnets may bear a distinct
relationship to what we do not know (which must be vastly more than
what we know) [my emphasis].
This is perilously close to an open
admission that the known facts do favor Oxford. In other words,
Nelson implies that the real case for William depends on facts that
arent available to us. This is the substance of his argument,
and its mighty peculiar scholarship hardly grounds for
ridiculing doubt of Williams authorship!
Why, after all, should we assume that
some nonexistent documents would prove Williams claim? If his
life had been more fully recorded, or if new documents were to turn up,
his claim might well be rendered totally untenable. Here Nelson posits a
bare possibility as a virtual fact. But virtual facts
dont count. In the real world, only real facts count; and Nelson
should have the candor to admit that the real facts, as we have them,
point to Oxford, since he implies as much when he equates the
positive evidence for Oxford with purely hypothetical
evidence for William. Yet he seems not to realize he has committed a fatal
faux pas. Nor does Gail Kern Paster.
Nelson displays peculiarly naive
scholarship when he asserts flatly that William was
prematurely balding by 1594, when the earliest Sonnets
were probably written. His baldness could explain why the poet
should feel old in comparison to a scarce-bearded youth of twenty-
one graced with flowing locks. There is no evidence at all for the
Premature Baldness Theory, a piece of tortured speculation which must be
counted as Nelsons indubitably original contribution to
Shakespeare scholarship. The poet speaks of his lameness
and his storm-beaten face (beated and chopped with
tanned antiquity), but not of losing his hair. (Oxford never went
bald; but then, je navais pas besoin de cette
hypothese-la.)
As far as I know, none of
Williams many biographers has ever suggested that William (who
is bald in the two surviving images of him) had lost his hair by 1594. If
they had, they probably wouldnt have thought it strengthened the
case that he wrote the Sonnets, or anything else. Perhaps only Nelson
would rest the weight of his argument on such a suppositious item, in the
face of so many facts of contrary import.
Nelson adds, just as flatly, that the
Sonnets are [not] by any means impossible to reconcile with the
little that is known about William. Really? Did William exaggerate
his age, go broke, become a pariah, and, for good measure, affect a limp?
He would have to do all these things in order to match the poet of the
Sonnets. As far as we know, he did none of them.
Since my thesis about the Sonnets is the
very heart of Alias Shakespeare, Nelsons denial that
the Sonnets are impossible to reconcile with what is known
of William stands as the crucial assertion of his review. Yet he offers
nothing to support it, beyond his bizarre suggestion that Williams
hypothetical premature baldness might help explain the poems.
Even here, however, Nelson is only
playing for a tie. He doesnt deny that the poets self-
portrait in the Sonnets matches Oxford; he merely says it may somehow
match William just as well. We are left to wonder how. If only we
had those nonexistent documents!
If William were the author, wed
expect his advocates to argue something like this: The Sonnets
match Williams known life so closely as to leave no serious doubt
of his authorship. They not only dont match what we know of
Oxfords life, they positively contradict it. But
Williams advocates never say this, for the simplest of reasons:
its patently untrue. The Sonnets contradict Williams known
life, not Oxfords. Wherefore Williams advocates edge away
from the first-person Sonnets, which you might expect them to cite
eagerly as the best evidence for his claim.
As Bernard Shaw remarks somewhere, a
mans real beliefs are best inferred not from the creed he
professes, but from the assumptions on which he habitually acts. Though
Williams academic partisans profess absolute confidence in his
authorship, they habitually act on the assumption that the Sonnets are
dangerous ground for their case, like an attorney who seeks to suppress
evidence damaging to his client. After all, the Sonnets are real documents,
as opposed to nonexistent ones.
Doggedly misstating my argument, Nelson
accuses me of
self-contradiction for saying both that Elizabethan and Jacobean readers
werent curious about authors and that its
significant that in an age of effusive eulogies, nobody bothered to
salute William when he died in 1616. But eulogies to dead poets
rarely supplied much information about them; they were merely occasions
of praise, not biography. The point is that when William died, the poets of
London didnt behave as if Shakespeare had died.
For good measure, Nelson adds a
hopelessly muddled paraphrase of my closing chapter, proving only that he
hasnt read Venus and Adonis which he
somehow thinks I assume would proclaim to the reading
public its authors homosexual leanings. The point of the alias, I
suggest, was to conceal those leanings, by disguising
Oxfords love of Southampton as the devotion of a common poet
some unknown novice named William Shakespeare
to his patron. Reasoning with his usual rigor, Nelson thinks I
assume that Venus would have told the public
that William was (or could have been) homosexual.
Nonsense. I assume exactly the opposite that the reading public
would suspect nothing untoward about an author whose name was obscure.
I merely think Oxford wanted to avoid exposing his own association with
Southampton, for fear of scandal and gossip.
Nelson doesnt grasp that you
cant refute an opponents argument unless you can first
state it in his own words, or words he would accept. Nor does he grasp
that not all facts are equally pertinent to the argument, or that piling on
irrelevant facts is precisely what distinguishes pedantry from
scholarship. Even an academic scholar should appreciate the importance of
simply sticking to the point.
But let us turn to what the Sonnets tell
us.
The poet who speaks in the Sonnets
describes himself as old (Oxford was in his forties,
fourteen years older than William), lame (Oxford often
described himself as lame and a lame man),
poor (Oxford had wasted his huge fortune), and
despised (Oxford had lived a scandalous life the one
thing Nelson is willing to give him credit for). The poet uses more than
200 legal terms, 50 of which also appear in Oxfords letters. (He
was trained in the law.)
The theme of the poets disgrace
has been neglected by academic commentators on the Sonnets, but
its all-important. The poet is in disgrace with fortune and
mens eyes; over and over he speaks of his
shame, his bewailed guilt, his outcast
state, his blots and stains, his being
despised and vile esteemed, the
vulgar scandal he has incurred, his name
having received a brand, his infection,
harmful deeds, errors, and
abuses. (About the only thing he never accuses himself of is
baldness.) He urges his young lover to forget him after his death, and even
to avoid being observed mourning him, lest the poets infamy harm
the younger mans reputation too. He thinks his disgrace is not only
terminal, but contagious.
Apparently the poet is a public figure
whose reputation has suffered some serious wound; he is obsessed with
his disgrace, referring to it more than a dozen times from Sonnet 25 to
Sonnet 121. After a life of scandal, Oxford was taunted about his
decayed reputation. One amour with a young lady at court,
which produced his bastard son, had landed him in the Tower of London, at
the queens order; at about the same time, he was accused of
pederasty; soon afterward he and his servitors got into violent
altercations with his former mistresss kinsmen, in one of which
he was seriously wounded.
Oxfords disgrace proved a social
and pecuniary handicap, denying him respect among his peers as well as
opportunities for lucrative employment, which he was reduced to begging
for after his reckless depletion of his family fortune. His deep humiliation
goes far toward explaining why he might conceal his authorship of any
works he might publish, and why he might write poems lamenting his
decline. The poet of the Sonnets looks forward to his death in the tone of a
ruined man whose prospects are all bleak; he has no trace of the optimism
of a young writer enjoying early success and fame, such as William,
according to the orthodox account, is supposed to have been.
The poets despair about his
reputation may be not impossible to reconcile with the
documented life of William, but its up to Nelson the scholar to
explain how; yet he offers not a syllable of explanation. He assumes that
the reader will accept his flat scholarly declaration as
sufficient.
Nelson does hint at a possible alternative
reading of the Sonnets when he accuses me of interpreting their implied
story with supreme literalness and failing to perceive their
hyperbole. Here Nelson means to suggest that the poet
cant always be taken literally and that whenever he sounds like
Oxford, he must be speaking figuratively. Once more, Nelson, according to
his habit, gives no specific examples of my confusing the literal with the
figurative; he merely hopes to plant the suspicion that all the
poets reiterated references to his age, disgrace, lameness,
poverty, et cetera, are mere rhetorical tropes. (If, on the other hand, the
poet had alluded to his baldness, that would clinch the case for
William!)
The poet seems to be bisexual, as he
falls in love with a lovely boy but also has a mistress.
Oxford had at least one mistress, and he was accused of buggering
boys a taste he was supposed to have picked up in Italy,
where pederasty was rife during the Renaissance. If William was bisexual,
it would of course be unlikely for any evidence of it to survive in the
documents of his life; but at any rate, none has.
If, as seems certain, the youth of the
Sonnets was Southampton, other things fall into place. The first seventeen
Sonnets urge the beautiful youth to marry; in the early 1590s the
handsome Southampton was pressured by Burghley to marry Elizabeth
Vere, Oxfords daughter. Why would William care whether
Southampton married Oxfords daughter? Like Oxford, moreover,
Southampton would later be accused of homosexual behavior. The poet
implies that he is old enough to be the youths father; Oxford was
twenty-three years older than Southampton. (William was a mere nine
years older.) Only a man of Oxfords rank might speak freely to the
Earl of Southampton in the loving (and sometimes scolding) tones of the
Sonnets; the poets plea for a grandchild Make thee
another self for love of me (Sonnet 10) would be
inexplicable coming from William.
There are other hints of the poets
rank: he says he prefers the youths love to high birth
(Sonnet 91), and he has bor[n]e the canopy (Sonnet 125),
perhaps the sort of ceremonial function Oxford, as hereditary Lord Great
Chamberlain, performed at court. Unlike William, the poet is sufficiently
well known to have incurred vulgar scandal (Sonnet 112);
there is a suggestion that the scandal was sexual (Sonnet 121).
Furthermore, the poet is confident that
his verse will be immortal, outlasting marble and the
gilded monument of princes. At the same time, he hopes that my
name [will] be buried where my body is (Sonnet 72) and that he will
be forgotten after his death (Sonnet 81). If he is William of
Stratford, publishing acclaimed poems under his real name, what could he
possibly mean by these tortured words? But if the poet was Oxford, they
not only make obvious sense, but describe precisely what has
happened.
The leitmotif of disgrace (unique in
Elizabethan sonnetry) recurs throughout the Sonnets and helps define the
poets relation to the youth, yet Nelson refuses to confront it at all.
He prefers to stick to his own specialty, irrelevant factual nit-picking.
Like most tax-subsidized academics (he teaches at Berkeley), he is too
timid to break from the pack. To deal with the Sonnets in toto would
require him to violate the Great Taboo of academic scholarship by
admitting that, yes, a plausible case for Oxford can be made from the
Sonnets and that it deserves an honest answer on its own grounds.
No Shakespeare scholar who values his career salary, tenure,
grants, sabbaticals, and other perks would grant the enemy such a
point. Nelson dutifully avoids dealing with the many facts that are
inconvenient to the scholarly position.
True, it is not impossible
to reconcile all this with Williams known life; but it puts quite a
strain on logic and common sense. As of the early 1590s, William,
whatever the condition of his hairline, would not appear to have been a
notorious public figure, distinguished by lameness, knowledge of the law,
and a bleak sense of his future, who would, despite his intimations of
mortality, take a keen interest in a young noblemans marital
prospects. Anyway, why should Southampton value or solicit
Williams advice on his personal life?
Like many academic Shakespeare
scholars, Nelson has only a superficial familiarity with the Sonnets. But
he cites with pedantic pride the utterly irrelevant information that their
scheduled publication was recorded in the Stationers
Register on 20 May 1609, while Edward Alleyn subsequently purchased a
copy for 5d.... [Five] copies survive from an issue sold by William Aspley,
eight from an issue sold by John Wright. Thanks, Professor!
Here Nelson is seeking to refute another
point I didnt make. He misses the mark again. Come to think of it,
the fact that the earliest edition of the Sonnets seems to have sold well
merely underlines the mystery of why no second edition appeared for more
than thirty years.
Nelson reveals his ignorance of the
Sonnets history when he writes that Shakespeares
Sonnets were publicly reported eleven years earlier to have been
circulating among his private friends. This of course refers to
Francis Meres, who wrote in 1598 of Shakespeares sugared
sonnets among his private friends. But were those
sugared sonnets the Sonnets published in 1609? To me it
seems doubtful, partly because sugared hardly seems the
word for poems so full of agony, regret, and intimate sexual matters. But
one should at least be aware of the long dispute on this question. Nelson is
not. He actually thinks the poet may not have been ...
mortified by the unauthorized publication of his homosexual love
poems!
Being ill acquainted with the Sonnets
themselves the most crucial evidence for purposes of identifying
Shakespeare Nelson ducks all their apparent links to Oxford, with
his offhand (and unsupported) claim that they are not
impossible to connect to William. Instead of presenting and
evaluating the evidence fully, he adopts the time-honored tactic
(Id hardly call it scholarly) of pretending it
isnt there. The contents of the Sonnets dont interest him
much, but he tries to bluff the reader with impressive
scholarly arcana about their publication.
Even so, Nelson actually makes a subtle
tacit admission when he asserts that the Sonnets are not
impossible to reconcile with Williams known life. This
implicitly concedes that they can be more easily reconciled with
Oxfords known life than with Williams. Nor does Nelson
deny, in any way, that they seem fully compatible with what we know
about Oxford. But of course he wont say this directly. The same is
true of the other academic critics of Alias Shakespeare:
none of them has challenged my thesis that the Sonnets seem to fit
everything we know about Oxford and virtually nothing we
know about William. In the authorship debate, its important to
notice not only what Williams advocates say, but what they go out
of their way not to say. At all costs, they must refuse to admit
difficulties for their position which they like to call
scholarly consensus.
Seizing on the bisexual theme, Nelson
asks, with triumphant glee, how on earth Oxford could have an amour with
his daughters intended husband: Did Oxford intend to share
Southamptons embraces with his own daughter? Were they to take
turns? Draw straws? Sobran doesnt say. But an attentive
reading of Alias Shakespeare makes it clear that the poet
begins to woo the youth for himself in Sonnet 20, by which time the theme
of marriage (which dominates the first 17 Sonnets) has been dropped; and
even then he intimates, at first, that his love isnt sexual. As I read
the Sonnets, Oxford and Southampton became lovers only when there was
no longer the prospect of a marriage between Southampton and Elizabeth
Vere. Nelson might have figured this out by studying the Sonnets
themselves.
Finally, Alias Shakespeare
shows that the Sonnets bear dozens of striking resemblances, in
vocabulary, imagery, theme, and argument, to Oxfords 1573 letter
to Bedingfield. But here again Nelson refuses to engage the details and
explain so many parallels; he doesnt even mention the ample
evidence cited in my book another omission that does no credit to
his scholarly honesty. He merely sneers that the letter is a dense
thicket of literary banality, as if belittling Oxford somehow counts
as an argument against his authorship.
Nelsons argument amounts to this
silly enthymeme: I say Oxford was a lousy writer; ergo he
couldnt have been Shakespeare. This is a rank fallacy, with
zero probative value. One might as well argue: The Shakespeare
works are so bad that Oxford couldnt have written them.
But of course such subjective judgments have no weight, and nothing
follows from them.
In the poets self-revelations, the
Sonnets give us a recognizable profile of Oxford; they yield no such profile
of William. This is why so many scholars, despairing of connecting them
to William, have asserted that they are fictions, though
they show none of Shakespeares gifts for narrative,
characterization, and exposition. If we recognize the Sonnets as
Oxfords, we have no need to resort to the idea that they are
fictions. Besides, even if they were fictions written by
William, why would he create a fictional first-person speaker who just
happens to resemble, among all his contemporaries, the Earl of
Oxford?
The key point is that none of
Williams champions have found a way to use the Sonnets to make a
positive case for his authorship. The Sonnets support the case for
Oxford and nobody else. I repeat: the orthodox scholars treat these poems
in much the way a defense attorney treats an incriminating document;
they try to declare them inadmissible evidence. If they really believed in
Williams authorship, they would cite parallels to Williams
life in the Sonnets, while citing details that are hard to reconcile with
Oxfords life. But they cant. An attorney tries to exclude
evidence when he senses that it would tend to hurt his client.
Finally, one more pregnant fact merits
our attention.
The first two published Shakespeare
works, Venus and Adonis (1593) and The Rape of
Lucrece (1594), were dedicated to Southampton at about the time
Burghley was pushing him to marry Oxfords daughter (and
Burghleys granddaughter) Elizabeth. The 1623 Folio was dedicated
to the Herbert brothers, William and Philip, earls of Pembroke and
Montgomery, who also had connections to Oxford. William had once been
considered as a possible husband for Oxfords daughter Bridget;
Philip had actually married Oxfords daughter Susan.
So all three of the men to whom the
Shakespeare works were dedicated by name had been candidates for the
hands of Oxfords three daughters!
It is not impossible, as
Nelson might say, that this is sheer coincidence, and that the hundreds of
other Oxford-Shakespeare links are also purely coincidental. But how
extraordinary (1) that William should write plays such as
Hamlet and the Italian plays, suggesting the privileged
education, special knowledge, and idiosyncratic personal experience
Oxford would have acquired more naturally; (2) that William should write
Sonnets whose main character bears so many resemblances to
Oxfords tormented life; and (3) that Williams works should
be dedicated to three of Oxfords prospective sons-in-law.
Well, anything is possible or at
least not impossible.
December 1999
|